The Mind

The mind is one thing that has always fascinated and puzzled us. It is the only thing that we can be certain of existing, yet, apparently, we do not know exactly what it is, how it occurs, and why it occurs. This is in contrast to things outside the mind, such as houses, cars, and even other people, which we cannot be certain that they really exist—they may be just illusions—yet, apparently, we know what they are, how they occur, and why they occur. What is more, the phenomena of qualia and consciousness, such as the red color as it appears phenomenally red in our mind and our phenomenal conscious awareness and experience of that red color, have always been baffling—what is their nature, how and why do they occur, and cannot there be just the mind without them?

Fortunately, with centuries of studying these matters, first by philosophers and later also by neuroscientists, psychologists, and other scientists in related fields, we now have a wealth of scientific evidence and concepts that are complete enough to form a theory that can answer these great puzzles.

“The Basic Theory of the Mind” is a physical theory about the mind and its phenomena, especially qualia and consciousness, derived from this wealth of knowledge. It also involves related matters, including the hard problem of consciousness, the explanatory gap, variable qualia, and p-zombies. As a physical theory, it provides empirically verifiable predictions. Its essence is as follows:

I. What is the mind?

The answer: From the similar physical properties of the mind and those of the brain’s information-processing process, such as being dynamic, continuously changing in the time scale of milliseconds, consisting of non-material content that can represent various things, and being able to communicate the content between their parts, it can be concluded that the mind is the brain’s information-processing process.

The mind is a composite of neural information processing processes

“What happens when we see, hear, and smell things around us, think about something, plan actions, experience moods, remember and recall events, and command our hands, lips, and body to move,

if not information, information, and information are being processed.

We are just informational entities, ever processing information and living on the informational side of the universe.”

Because the mind is the brain’s information-processing process, it is an informational entity. Because it is a non-material, informational entity, it is not composed of elementary particles and their interactions, which constitute conventional physical entities (or mechanical entities) like mass, energy, or force. That is why the mind is so different from conventional physical entities.

II. Why do we have minds, qualia, and consciousness as they are—manifesting phenomenally as visions, sounds, smells, tastes, emotions, thoughts, etc. that we can experience richly in our lives? Why are we not like computers or robots, doing everything “in the dark” without those phenomena occurring?

Qualia & consciousness in humans vs robots

The answer is that such minds, qualia, and consciousness have physical effects that increase the survival chances of ourselves and our species. Therefore, minds, qualia, and consciousness as they are—manifesting phenomenally—exist to help us and our species survive with better chances.

III. How can minds, qualia, and consciousness have physical effects?

The answer is by inducing occurrences and functions of physical processes. Evidently, when minds, qualia, and consciousness occur, we have awareness and experiences of them. We can tell that they have happened and what they are like … what visions are like, what sounds are like, what smells are like, what emotions are like, what thoughts are like, etc. But awareness and experiences cannot occur alone by themselves—some brain processes must function for them to occur. Hence, minds, qualia, and consciousness must induce brain processes to occur and perform these functions. Since brain processes are physical, minds, qualia, and consciousness induce physical processes and thus have physical effects.

IV. But how can something with phenomenal manifestations, such as the vision of a house, the sound of a song, and the smell of a rose … in our minds, occur from brain processes, which are physical and do not have phenomenal manifestations?

Qualia and consciousness

The answer is that some brain processes have signals that mean, among working brain processes, something with phenomenal manifestations, such as the vision of a house. When viewed from the third-person point of view—our point of view when we think about or investigate the signals in labs—they do not appear to be something with phenomenal manifestations because they are only thought about or observed, not read. In contrast, when viewed from the first-person point of view—the natural point of view of working brain processes—the signals are read and interpreted. If the signals mean something with phenomenal manifestation, the reading brain processes will interpret them as such. Consequently, something with phenomenality, such as the vision of a house, naturally and inevitably appears in those neural processes and the brain.

[Quick proof ⇒ Qualia have physical effects]

[Quick proof ⇒ Qualia are neural signals]

V. How can physical signals have such meanings? What are the ontological and physical nature of minds, qualia, and consciousness? Do other animals, robots, and other things have them?

The answers to these questions and other related problems can be found scientifically. They are in this theory. The readers are kindly invited to explore them.

———————————-

The Three Great Problems of the Mind

1. The Ontological Problem of the Mind and its Phenomena

2. The Hard Problem of Consciousness

3. The Explanatory Gap of Consciousness

These three puzzles are some of the most important in science and philosophy … and our lives. The solutions to them can be found in this theory. Their concise summary is as follows:

1. Present evidence indicates that physical entities (entities obeying physical rules) interact only with physical entities. Because the mind, qualia, and consciousness interact with the brain, a physical entity, enabling us to be aware of and engage in various physical activities related to them (such as discussing, investigating, and documenting them), it is logical to deduce that they are physical entities. Otherwise, new laws for interactions between physical and non-physical entities must be added. Current evidence shows that the former possibility is tenable, and no new laws are needed. Based on their physical properties (such as being non-material, having content about something, and being closely associated with neural processes), it can be concluded that the mind, qualia, and consciousness are neural information—a physical entity—in various forms (as specified in the theory). Because neural information inherently exists in the processing brain, no novel entities are created to be the mind, qualia, or consciousness. This conclusion answers the ontological question of what these three entities are and the hard problem of how these seemingly non-physical entities can occur in the brain.

2. In the third-person point of view, our point of view when we think about or investigate it in the labs, information does not appear as something with phenomenal manifestations, such as qualia and consciousness, because it is not read and interpreted but only thought about or observed. In contrast, in the first-person point of view, the natural point of view of working neural processes, information is read and interpreted. If it means something with phenomenal manifestations, it will be interpreted as such. Consequently, something with phenomenal manifestations, such as qualia and consciousness, will and must appear in the reading neural processes and the brain. This point-of-view account bridges the explanatory gap of how qualia and consciousness can occur in the brain and explains how we can feel and experience ourselves and everything else phenomenally as we do, even though we are merely some forms of information.

3. Since it is a brute fact that the mind, qualia, and consciousness can occur in this universe, at least in some living things, they eventually appeared in organisms that evolved structures complex enough to support them, such as the brain. Their first appearances on this planet were no later than when Homo sapiens, a species possessing them, emerged around 200,000 to 300,000 years ago. Because they exhibit themselves as observable characteristics, they require resources for their generation, expression, and maintenance. Moreover, they may have adverse effects. Therefore, if their overall effects are not beneficial to the species’ survival, both these characteristics and the species possessing them will become extinct due to competition with similar species that do not possess them, such as the original species. This principle is especially true for major characteristics in a critical organ, such as the mind, qualia, and consciousness in the brain, because they expend significant resources. The continued existence of these characteristics over at least hundreds of thousands of years means that they have been preserved through the evolutionary process. With the human race flourishing, not withering, this persistence indicates that their overall effects must aid in humans’ survival. Therefore, the mind, qualia, and consciousness evolved in species, including ours, to help increase the species’ survival chances. This inference answers the hard problem of why they occur in us.

———————————-

To continue reading the synopsis of the theory, please click: Synopsis

To begin reading the theory in a webpage format, please click: Introduction and Definitions

To freely download the PDF version of the theory, please click: Download the PDF version

For readers interested in some specific subjects, specific links to them are as follows:

—————————–

In the end, it can be concluded that

We as we are—with minds, qualia, and consciousness—

exist to increase the survival chances of our species

… and ourselves.

You, as you are—with your mind, qualia, and consciousness—

exist to increase the survival chances of your species

… and yourself.


The Basic Theory of the Mind: The book.

The First Hardcover Edition (2018)

The Basic Theory of the Mind - The printed book

The Basic Theory of the Mind - Front & Back

Look inside the book

The first edition is now out of stock.


The Second Hardcover Edition (2024)

The Basic Theory of the Mind - the book

The second edition has been published.


The theory has also been published as Kindle eBooks, and two editions are now available on Amazon Kindle.

The First Kindle Edition (2020)

The Basic Theory of the Mind - Kindle ebook edition

Buy the first Kindle edition at Amazon Kindle

The Second Kindle Edition (2024)

The Basic Theory of the Mind - Kindle ebook

Buy the second Kindle edition at Amazon Kindle

However, as noted above, a PDF version of the book’s second edition is available for free at:  Download the PDF version.


> Go to Introduction and Definitions


Bibliography

Bennett MR. Development of the concept of mind. Aust N Z J Psychiatry. 2007 Dec;41(12):943-956.

Block N. Comparing the major theories of consciousness. In: Gazzaniga MS, editor. The Cognitive Neurosciences (Chap 77). 4th ed., Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 2009:1111–1122. https://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/Theories_of_Consciousness.pdf

Block N. Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2007;30(5–6):481–499. https://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/Block_BBS.pdf

Brogaard B, Electra Gatzia DE. What can neuroscience tell us about the hard problem of consciousness? Front Neurosci. 2016;10:395. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2016.00395.  https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5013033/

Chalmers DJ. Consciousness and its place in nature. In: Chalmers DJ, editor. Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2002. ISBN-13: 978-0195145816 ISBN-10: 019514581X. http://consc.net/papers/nature.html

Chalmers DJ. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud. 1995;2(3):200-219. http://consc.net/papers/facing.html

Chalmers DJ. Moving forward on the problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud. 1997;4(1):3-46. http://consc.net/papers/moving.html

Chalmers DJ. Phenomenal concepts and the explanatory gap. In: Alter T, Walter S, editors. Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism. Oxford University Press; 2006. https://www.sciencedharma.com/uploads/7/6/8/0/76803975/pceg.pdf

Chalmers DJ. The puzzle of conscious experience. Sci Am. 1995 Dec;273(6):80–86. http://s3.amazonaws.com/arena-attachments/2382142/9247d5f1a845e5482b1bd66d82c3a9bf.pdf?1530582615

Chalmers DJ. What is a neural correlate of consciousness? In: Metzinger T, editor. Neural Correlates of Consciousness: Empirical and Conceptual Questions. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. 2000. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/35c4/ecd86863e84d2b2b0a31294b7b0223d7204e.pdf

Chalmers DJ. The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press;1996. https://personal.lse.ac.uk/ROBERT49/teaching/ph103/pdf/Chalmers_The_Conscious_Mind.pdf

Cohen MA, Dennett DC. Consciousness cannot be separated from function. Trends Cogn Sci. 2011 Aug;15(8):358–364. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2011.06.008. http://www.michaelacohen.net/uploads/5/9/0/7/59073133/1-s2-0-s1364661311001252-main.pdf

Coseru C. Mind in Indian Buddhist Philosophy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/mind-indian-buddhism

Crick F, Koch C. Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Seminars in the Neurosciences. 1990;2:263–275. https://authors.library.caltech.edu/40352/1/148.pdf

De Sousa A. Towards an integrative theory of consciousness: Part 1 (neurobiological and cognitive models). Mens Sana Monogr. 2013 Jan-Dec;11(1):100-150. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3653219/

Dehaene S, Charles L, King JR, Marti S. Toward a computational theory of conscious processing. Curr Opin Neurobiol. 2014 Apr;25:76–84. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2013.12.005. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5635963/

Dehaene S, Lau H, Kouider S. What is consciousness, and could machines have it? Science. 2017 Oct 27;358(6362):486-492. doi: 10.1126/science.aan8871. http://www.casinapioiv.va/content/accademia/en/publications/scriptavaria/artificial_intelligence/dehaene.pdf

Dennett DC. Facing up to the hard question of consciousness. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2018;373(1755):20170342. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2017.0342. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6074080/?report=classic

Dolan B. Soul searching: A brief history of the mind/body debate in the neurosciences. Neurosurg Focus. 2007;23(1):E2. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/0ee7/daa68d6c67564e9778c9c4426988a7e6a0b9.pdf?_ga=2.218379610.273739394.1573212485-1576401793.1567926358

Edelman GM. Naturalizing consciousness: A theoretical framework. PNAS. 2003 April 29;100(9):5520-5524. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0931349100 https://www.pnas.org/content/100/9/5520

Edelman GM, Gally JA, Baars BJ. Biology of Consciousness. Front Psychol. 2011;2:4. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3111444/

Feigl H. The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical’. In: Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem. University of Minnesota Press. 1958. https://conservancy.umn.edu/handle/11299/184614

Feinberg TE, Mallatt J. Phenomenal consciousness and emergence: Eliminating the explanatory gap. Front Psychol. 2020;11:1041. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01041. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7304239/

Feinberg TE, Mallatt J. The nature of primary consciousness. A new synthesis. Conscious Cogn. 2016;43:113–127. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2016.05.009. https://www.gwern.net/docs/psychology/2016-feinberg.pdf

Fieser J. Chapter 3: Mind. Great Issues in Philosophy. 2021 Jan 1. http://edduarddo1000.freehostia.com/filosofiapdf/what%20is%20a%20mind.pdf

Fink SB. A Deeper Look at the “Neural Correlate of Consciousness.” Front Psychol. 2016; 7: 144. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01044. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4960249/

Gennaro RJ. Consciousness. In: The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/consciou/

Giannetti E. The possibility of physicalism. Dement Neuropsychol. 2011 Oct-Dec;5(4):42–250.
doi: 10.1590/S1980-57642011DN05040002. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5619037/

Grossberg S. Towards solving the hard problem of consciousness: The varieties of brain resonances and the conscious experiences that they support. Neural Netw. 2017 Mar;87:38-95. https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0893608016301800?via%3Dihub

Kanai R, Tsuchiya N. Qualia. Current Biology. 2012 May;22(10):392–396. http://www.cell.com/current-biology/fulltext/S0960-9822(12)00320-X

Koch C, Massimini M, Boly M, Tononi G. Neural correlates of consciousness: progress and problems. Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 2016;17: 307-321.

Kulstad M and Carlin L. Leibniz’s Philosophy of Mind. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/leibniz-mind/

Levine J. Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 1983;64:354–361. https://hope.simons-rock.edu/~pshields/cs/cmpt265/levine.pdf

Llinás R, Ribary U, Contreras D, Pedroarena C. The neuronal basis for consciousness. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 1998 Nov 29;353(1377):1841–1849. doi: 10.1098/rstb.1998.0336. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1692417/pdf/9854256.pdf

Loorits K. Structural qualia: A solution to the hard problem of consciousness. Front Psychol. 2014;5:237. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00237. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3957492/

Mainzer K. The emergence of mind and brain: an evolutionary, computational, and philosophical approach. Prog Brain Res. 2008;168:115-32. doi: 10.1016/S0079-6123(07)68010-8. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/18166390

McLear C. Kant: Philosophy of Mind. https://www.iep.utm.edu/kandmind/

Nagel T. What is the mindbody problem? Ciba Found Symp1993;174:17; discussion 713

Orpwood R. Information and the origin of qualia. Front Syst Neurosci. 2017 Apr 21;11(Article 22):1–16. doi: 10.3389/fnsys.2017.00022  https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5399078/pdf/fnsys-11-00022.pdf

Orpwood R. Neurobiological mechanisms underlying qualia. J Integr Neurosci. 2007 Dec;6(4):523-540.

Papineau D. Mind the gap. Philosophical Perspectives. 1998;12:373–389. https://sas-space.sas.ac.uk/878/1/D_Papineau_Gap..pdf  http://www.davidpapineau.co.uk/uploads/1/8/5/5/18551740/mind_the_gap.pdf

Pandya SK. Understanding brain, mind and soul: contributions from neurology and neurosurgery. Mens Sana Monogr. 2011 Jan;9(1):129-49. doi: 10.4103/0973-1229.77431.  https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3115284/

Place UT. Is consciousness a brain process? Br J Psychol. 1956;47(1):44-50.

Pernu TK. The five marks of the mental. Front Psychol. 2017;8:1084. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01084. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5500963/

Polák M, Marvan T. Neural correlates of consciousness meet the Theory of Identity. Front Psychol. 2018; 9: 1269. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01269 https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6066586/

Riekki T, Lindeman M, Lipsanen J. Conceptions about the mind-body problem and their relations to afterlife beliefs, paranormal beliefs, religiosity, and ontological confusions. Adv Cogn Psychol. 2013;9(3):112–120. doi: 10.2478/v10053-008-0138-5. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4158462/ 

Rosenthal D. Concepts and Definitions of Consciousness. In: Banks WP, editor. Encyclopedia of Consciousness. Amsterdam: Elsevier; 2009:157-169. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/280529005_Concepts_and_Definitions_of_Consciousness_in_Encyclopedia_of_Consciousness_ed_William_P_Banks_Amsterdam_Elsevier_2009_pp_157-169

Scholarpedia. Model of consciousness. http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/Models_of_consciousness

Schneider S. Identity theory. In: The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/identity/

Seager W. Theories of consciousness. An introduction and assessment. 2nd edNew York, NY: Routledge; 2016. ISBN 978-0-415-83409-4.

Seth AK. Consciousness: The last 50 years (and the next). Brain and Neuroscience Advances. 2018; 2 Jan 1. https://doi.org/10.1177/2398212818816019 https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/full/10.1177/2398212818816019

Seth AK, Baars BJ. Neural Darwinism and consciousness. Conscious Cogn. 2005 Mar;14(1):140–168. http://ccrg.cs.memphis.edu/assets/papers/2004/Seth%20&%20Baars,%20Neural%20Darwinism-2004.pdf

Seth AK, Izhikevich E, Reeke GN, Edelman GM. Theories and measures of consciousness: An extended framework. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA. 2006 Jul; 103(28): 10799-10804. doi:10.1073/pnas.0604347103.  https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1487169/

Smart JJC. The mind/brain identity theory. Zalta EN, editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition).  https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/mind-identity/

Sturm T. Consciousness regained? Philosophical arguments for and against reductive physicalism. Dialogues Clin Neurosci. 2012 Mar;14(1):55-63. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3341650/

Tye M. Qualia. In: Zalta EN, editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/qualia/

Van Gulick R. Consciousness. Zalta EN, editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/consciousness

Velmans M. Chapter 1. How to separate conceptual issues from empirical ones in the study of consciousness. In: Banerjee R, Chakrabarti BK, editors. Models of Brain and Mind: Physical, Computational and Psychological Approaches. Amsterdam: Elsevier. 2007;168:1-9. ISBN: 978-0-444-53050-9. ISSN: 0079-6123.

Velmans M. How to define consciousness – and how not to define consciousness. J Conscious Stud. 2009;16(5):139-156. http://cogprints.org/6453/1/How_to_define_consciousness.pdf

Velmans M. Understanding consciousness. 2nd ed. Hove, East Sussex: Routledge; 2009. https://dl.uswr.ac.ir/bitstream/Hannan/130278/1/0415425158.Routledge.Understanding.Consciousness.Second.Edition.Apr.2009.pdf

Weisberg J. The hard problem of consciousness. In: The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://www.iep.utm.edu/hard-con/

Zeman A. What do we mean by “conscious” and “aware”? Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2006 Aug;16(4):356-76. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/16864477


Synopsis

Based on the wealth of scientific evidence and concepts, this theory has been formed, and its essence is as follows:

1. From the physical properties of the mind and those of the brain (the alive, processing brain), it can be concluded that the mind occurs, exists, and functions with the brain (Chapter 1) and that it is the composite of all neural information-processing processes (Chapter 2).

“What happens when we see, hear, and smell things around us, experience moods, think of various things, plan appropriate actions, and command our hands, lips, and body to move, if not information, information, and information are being processed.

We are just informational entities, ever processing information and living on the informational side of the universe.”

Because the mind is a composite of neural information-processing processes, it is an informational entity—a non-material entity that is composed of information and information processing, and because the information-processing processes that form the mind are innumerable and involve information that ranges from simple to very advanced, the mind is an informational entity in a highly advanced form. Because the mind is a non-material, informational entity, it is not composed of elementary particles and their interactions, which constitute conventional physical entities (or mechanical entities) like mass, energy, or force. That is why the mind is so different from conventional physical entities. (Chapter 2)

2. Qualia—mental phenomena that appear phenomenally in our mind and that we can consciously experience, such as the vision of a house, the sound of a song, and the odor of a rose in our mind—are physical phenomena. They are governed by physical laws and are physically predictable. Specifically, they are neural-process–associated physical phenomena. (Chapters 3 & 4)

3. From the physical properties of qualia and those of special kinds of neural-process signaling patterns, which are neural information and non-material, it can be concluded that qualia are special kinds of neural-process signaling patterns, called special signaling patterns. (Chapter 5)

“If we open our eyes and experience visual qualia occurring right in front of us now, 

with the fact that we can experience qualia only if the brain can experience the qualia,

it is inescapable to conclude that we are, in fact, experiencing neural signaling patterns

because the only things the brain can experience—read and process—are neural signaling patterns!”

Because neural-process signaling patterns are neural information, qualia are special kinds of neural information—information in specialized forms that, when read by neural processes, are interpreted as phenomenal qualia or qualia that appear phenomenally in our mind.

Like the mind, qualia are non-material, informational entities, not mechanical entities. The fact that qualia are neural signaling patterns answers the hard problem of qualia and bridges the explanatory gap of how non-material phenomenal qualia can arise from material neural processes: Non-material phenomenal qualia are neural signaling patterns, which always exist intrinsically in material neural processes—no novel, non-material entities arise or emerge from material neural processes to be qualia. (Chapter 5)

4. From the physical properties of consciousness and those of a special kind of reentrant signaling state, which is the neural information of the consciousness neural process and is non-material, it can be concluded that consciousness is a special kind of reentrant signaling state.

Because a neural-process signaling state is neural information, consciousness is a special kind of neural information—information in a specialized form that, when read by the consciousness neural process itself by the process of reentrant signaling, is interpreted as phenomenal consciousness or consciousness that appears phenomenally in our minds.

Like the mind and qualia, consciousness is a non-material, informational entity, not a mechanical entity. The fact that consciousness is a signaling state answers the hard problem of consciousness and bridges the explanatory gap of how non-material phenomenal consciousness can arise from the material consciousness neural process: Non-material phenomenal consciousness is the consciousness neural process’s signaling state, which always exists intrinsically in the material consciousness neural process—no novel, non-material entity arises or emerges from the material consciousness neural process to be consciousness. (Chapter 6)

5. The fact that qualia and conscious awareness and conscious experiences of the qualia occur in only the final-stage sensory perception neural processes and the highest-level cognitive and executive neural processes, which are the latest-evolved neural processes, and never occur in the more primitive neural processes, such as the brainstem, cerebellum, and basal ganglia, or over the whole brain randomly, indicates that they are not haphazardly occurring phenomena but are evolved phenomena of the nervous system. (Chapter 5 & Chapter 6)

6. Because a neural process that performs a certain function (such as perceiving a vision) without a quale occurring and a neural process that performs that same function (such as perceiving the same vision) with a quale occurring have different information in the processes, they have different signaling patterns (to convey different information). Therefore, they have different physical effects on other neural processes, at least from the different effects of different signaling patterns. Qualia thus have physical effects.

Also, because we do have conscious awareness and conscious experiences of qualia, qualia must certainly induce the consciousness neural process to function to be consciously aware of and to consciously experience the qualia. Therefore, because the consciousness neural process is a physical process, qualia cause changes in a physical process and thus have physical effects. (Chapter 5)

Similarly, it can be concluded that consciousness (conscious awareness and conscious experiences) has physical effects. (Chapter 6)

Therefore, qualia and consciousness are evolved neural functions that have physical effects.

7. Because a function requires resources in building, maintaining, and operating the function and may have some negative effects, if its overall effects do not help increase the survival chances of the animals that have the function, those animals and the function will likely become extinct in the evolutionary process. This is especially true for a major function in a critical organ, such as in the case of qualia and consciousness in the brain. The fact that qualia and consciousness still exist today indicates that they have been selected to remain in the evolutionary process. This means that their overall effects must help increase the survival chances of the species that have them. Qualia and consciousness, in the form that they are—phenomenal qualia and phenomenal consciousness, or qualia and consciousness that appear phenomenally in our mind—are thus evolved functions to help increase the survival chances of the species, including humans, that have them. This is the scientific answer to the other part of the hard problem of consciousness: Why do qualia and consciousness in the form of phenomenal qualia and phenomenal consciousness occur in this universe? This is also the scientific answer to one of the most basic questions of our lives: Why do “we” exist? (Chapter 5 & Chapter 6)

> Go to Introduction and Definitions


Keywords:

Mind, consciousness, qualia, quale, the hard problem of consciousness, the explanatory gap, the mind-body problem, theory of qualia, theory of consciousness, consciousness book, p-zombies, philosophical zombie, dualism, physicalism

Dr. Chirapat Ukachoke

Last revision – August 28, 2024